Home PeopleThomas Hobbes (1588–1679): Architect of Modern Political Philosophy

Thomas Hobbes (1588–1679): Architect of Modern Political Philosophy

by alan.dotchin

Thomas Hobbes was one of the most influential political philosophers of the early modern period. Best known for his masterpiece Leviathan (1651), Hobbes laid the groundwork for social contract theory and offered a secular, scientific view of politics that broke sharply from traditional and theological justifications for authority. His vision of human nature, sovereignty, and civil order continues to shape debates in political science, ethics, and philosophy.


1. Historical Context and Life

Hobbes was born on April 5, 1588, in Westport, Wiltshire, England—an event he famously linked to the looming threat of the Spanish Armada, saying that “fear and I were born twins.” His life spanned one of the most turbulent eras in English history, marked by civil wars, religious conflict, regicide, and the eventual Restoration.

Educated at Oxford, Hobbes became a tutor to the Cavendish family, which connected him to powerful patrons and European intellectuals. He traveled extensively across the continent and engaged with thinkers like René Descartes and Galileo Galilei, whose mechanical philosophy and scientific method deeply influenced his approach.

Hobbes’s experiences during the English Civil War (1642–1651) profoundly shaped his political thought. Witnessing the breakdown of authority and the horrors of anarchy, he became preoccupied with the need for strong, centralized government to ensure peace and prevent societal collapse.


2. Human Nature: Mechanism and Materialism

Central to Hobbes’s philosophy is his mechanistic view of the universe. Influenced by the new science of his time, especially Galileo’s physics, Hobbes rejected metaphysical explanations rooted in the soul or divine purpose. Instead, he saw all phenomena—including thought, sensation, and emotion—as the motion of matter.

Human beings, he argued, are essentially material organisms driven by appetite and aversion. We seek what we desire and avoid what we fear. There is no intrinsic good or evil; only what individuals perceive as conducive to their self-preservation.

This materialist psychology forms the basis of Hobbes’s ethical and political theories. Without a transcendent moral order, values must be derived from natural human impulses and needs—most importantly, the need for security and peace.


3. The State of Nature and the Social Contract

Hobbes’s most famous concept is the state of nature—a hypothetical pre-political condition in which there is no government, no laws, and no common authority.

In this state, Hobbes argues, humans are roughly equal in strength and cunning, which breeds mistrust and competition. Because each person seeks to preserve themselves and secure resources, life becomes a violent struggle of all against all:

“In such condition, there is no place for industry;… and the life of man, solitary, poor, nasty, brutish, and short.” (Leviathan, Ch. XIII)

To escape this miserable state, individuals enter into a social contract, agreeing to surrender their natural rights to a sovereign power in exchange for protection and peace. This agreement forms the basis of civil society.

Importantly, Hobbes believes that the contract is not between the people and the sovereign, but among the people themselves. They collectively authorize a ruler to wield absolute power on their behalf to maintain order.


4. Sovereignty and the Leviathan

In Leviathan, Hobbes outlines his vision of the ideal political structure. The sovereign—be it a monarch, an assembly, or a council—must possess absolute and indivisible authority. Hobbes was not inherently monarchist; he believed that the form of government was less important than its ability to command obedience and maintain peace.

The sovereign has the power to make laws, control the military, censor speech, and adjudicate disputes. Hobbes justifies this authoritarian model not by divine right, but by necessity: without a strong central authority, society would revert to chaos.

He famously likens the state to a Leviathan, a biblical sea monster, a metaphor for the immense, artificial person composed of its citizens, united under the sovereign’s rule:

“This is the generation of that great Leviathan… which is but an artificial man; though of greater stature and strength than the natural, for whose protection and defense it was intended.” (Leviathan, Introduction)


5. Religion and Politics

Hobbes’s views on religion were controversial and played a role in his reputation as an atheist or irreligious thinker, though he always denied this.

In Leviathan, Part III and IV, Hobbes critically examines the role of religious belief in politics. He argues that religious authority must be subordinated to civil authority to avoid division and conflict. He rejects the idea that priests or the Church have any divine right to political power.

Hobbes also challenges traditional theological doctrines, including miracles, angels, and the immortality of the soul. For him, much of religion could be explained through human fear of the unknown and desire for order—both of which, he believes, should be managed by the state rather than religious institutions.

By advocating a secular basis for sovereignty, Hobbes helped to separate church and state in modern political thought.


6. Liberty, Law, and the Individual

Though Hobbes is often viewed as an authoritarian thinker, his concept of liberty is nuanced. For Hobbes, freedom is not the absence of constraint, but the absence of external impediments to motion. In political terms, this means that liberty exists under the law, so long as one is not physically prevented from acting.

He acknowledges that the sovereign must limit some freedoms to preserve peace but insists that individuals retain certain inalienable rights—such as the right to self-preservation. If the sovereign threatens a person’s life unjustly, they are morally justified in resisting, even though rebellion generally leads to worse outcomes.

Hobbes’s view contrasts with later liberal thinkers like John Locke, who emphasized individual rights against the state. Still, Hobbes laid the groundwork for social contract theory that would shape liberal democratic theory for centuries.


7. Legacy and Influence

Thomas Hobbes’s influence on political philosophy is immense. He is widely considered one of the founding figures of modern political science, particularly for:

  • Secularizing political authority by grounding it in human nature and rational agreement rather than divine command.
  • Developing the social contract as a rational basis for legitimate government.
  • Anticipating realism in international relations theory, where the international system is seen as a state of nature requiring strategic power balances.

His work influenced a wide range of thinkers, including:

  • John Locke, who accepted the social contract but rejected Hobbes’s absolutism.
  • Jean-Jacques Rousseau, who also theorized the state of nature but saw it as less violent.
  • Carl Schmitt and Leo Strauss, 20th-century theorists who revisited Hobbes’s emphasis on order and sovereignty.
  • Modern political realists, like Hans Morgenthau and Kenneth Waltz, in their theories of power and security.

Hobbes also had a significant impact on the development of legal positivism, the view that laws are rules created by humans and not dependent on morality or divine will.


8. Criticisms

Hobbes has been criticized on several grounds:

  • His pessimistic view of human nature has been challenged by more optimistic or communitarian theories.
  • His support for absolute sovereignty is seen by many as dangerous or incompatible with liberty.
  • His dismissal of democratic participation and emphasis on obedience has been contested by liberal and republican theorists.

Nevertheless, his work remains essential reading for students of political theory, ethics, and early modern philosophy.


9. Conclusion

Thomas Hobbes was a bold and original thinker whose ideas revolutionized the way we understand authority, the state, and human nature. In a world torn by war and religious strife, he sought a rational, scientific basis for peace and social order. While some may balk at his authoritarian conclusions, his commitment to clarity, rigor, and realism helped to inaugurate the modern era of political thought.

“Covenants, without the sword, are but words, and of no strength to secure a man at all.” — Leviathan, Ch. XVII

In confronting the dark possibilities of human nature, Hobbes challenged us to rethink the foundation of society and the true conditions for freedom and security.

You may also like

Leave a Comment